stoutfellow: My summer look (Summer)
[personal profile] stoutfellow
We'll start examining 19th-century developments in analysis shortly, but I want to make a few observations concerning the importance of quantifiers before doing so.

There's a sharp distinction between terms - which, as I've said, must have a single definite reference - and quantified phrases. This is not merely the invention of logicians; ordinary language recognizes it.

Consider negation. In English, to negate a simple statement with no quantifiers is easy: if the verb is "to be" or one of the modals, we just insert "not" after the verb.
NOT(John is here) = John isn't here.
NOT(I can do this) = I can't do this.
Otherwise, we usually insert some form of "do".
NOT(I saw him) = I didn't see him.
NOT(I understand this) = I don't understand this.
But if quantifiers are involved, more complex manipulations are required.
NOT(Someone is here) = No one is here.
NOT(Everyone can do this) = Not everyone can do this = Some people can't do this.
And those are the easy ones; quantified statements involving "two", "a few", "exactly one", "most" and the like are notoriously hard to negate.

The point here is that, from a logical and linguistic standpoint, quantified statements are qualitatively different from statements without quantifiers. (That's not exactly news; the medieval syllogists distinguished both universal and particular statements from "individual" - i.e., unquantified - statements.) But there's more.

Abraham Lincoln is famously said to have said that "you can fool some of the people all of the time". (The evidence that he actually said this is, shall we say, slender.) It's actually not entirely clear what this claim means. Is it
(for some people x) (for all times t) you can fool x at t,
i.e., there are people you can always fool, or is it
(for all times t) (for some people x) you can fool x at t,
i.e., at any given time there are people you can fool?

This sort of ambiguity exists, at least potentially, every time a statement contains two quantifiers of different types. In fairness, I have to point out that - at least in English - it is normally dealt with by word order: "There are always people you can fool" vs. "There are people you can always fool", for example. The Lincoln quote is slightly aberrant in this respect, as it gives no clear indication of the resolution of the ambiguity.

Nonetheless, this points to a significant fact. Statements involving two quantifiers can be difficult to interpret; statements with more than that are even harder, unless careful attention is paid - e.g., by the explicit use of the quantifier symbolism devised by Pierce, or something like it. Modern mathematics leans heavily on multiple-quantifier statements; for example, the definition of a statement like "the function f(x) is continuous" involves four quantifiers, three of them universal and one existential. (The related but stronger statement "the function f(x) is uniformly continuous" turns out to differ only in the order of the quantifiers.) Mathematicians began working with these concepts well before Pierce's time, but it seems unlikely that the progress that was made in the twentieth century would have been possible without his work.

Previous Next

Ramble Contents

Date: 2008-09-21 12:50 am (UTC)
From: [identity profile] akatsukami.livejournal.com
Is it the underlying statement that is ambiguous, or is it that we haven't sufficiently defined the syntax?

In computer programming (and, IIRC, in mathematics), precedence is defined. The statement x=4*3+7; isn't ambiguous because multiplication takes precedence over addition (in most languages).

Too, you can always use parentheses to override "natural" precedence. In the statement x=4*(3+7);, x takes the value 40, not 19, because sub-expressions in the innermost parentheses (only one set in this example) are interpreted (or compiled :) ) first. Liberal use of parentheses in programming to eliminate ambiguity is considered virtuous, as not everyone remembers the precedence of operators in a language, and some may switch between several languages with different rules.

The statement Q1Q2S would always be interpreted unambiguously and in the same way by a compiler (granted, different compilers might interpret it differently, but any given compiler would always handle the same way).

Date: 2008-09-21 08:05 pm (UTC)
From: [identity profile] stoutfellow.livejournal.com
Is it the underlying statement that is ambiguous, or is it that we haven't sufficiently defined the syntax?

To say that the sentence is ambiguous is precisely to say that it's not clear what the underlying statement is. The problem is, indeed, at the syntax/semantics interface; English syntax has some tools for specifying the order of quantifiers, but the given sentence doesn't use them.

Any language or sublanguage that has to use quantifiers extensively is going to have syntactic devices - precedence, grouping symbols, etc. - to deal with the problem; the jargons of mathematics and computer science do, in particular. But in everyday language, multiple quantifiers come up rarely enough that the tools just aren't there.

Profile

stoutfellow: Joker (Default)
stoutfellow

April 2020

S M T W T F S
    1 2 34
5 6 789 1011
12 13 14 1516 17 18
19202122232425
2627282930  

Most Popular Tags

Style Credit

Expand Cut Tags

No cut tags
Page generated May. 25th, 2025 08:07 am
Powered by Dreamwidth Studios